What is pragmatics pdf


















Deliberation and Practical Reason. In Essays on Aristotles Ethics, edited by A. Berkeley: University of California Press, Williams, Bernard. Internal and External Reasons. In Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers, Cambridge, U.

Robert N. Johnson Morris as the branch of semiotics that studies the relation of signs to interpreters, in contrast with semantics, which studies the relation of signs to designata. There has been some doubt about whether it is a homogeneous domain Searle, Kiefer, and Bierwisch Grice showed that many aspects of utterance meaning traditionally regarded as conventional, or semantic, could be more explanatorily treated as conversational, or pragmatic.

For Gricean pragmatists, the crucial feature of pragmatic interpretation is its inferential nature: the hearer is seen as constructing and evaluating a hypothesis about the communicators intentions, based, on the one hand, on the meaning of the sentence uttered, and on the other, on contextual information and general communicative principles that speakers are normally expected to observe. For definition and surveys see Levinson In early work, the semantics-pragmatics distinction was often seen as coextensive with the distinction between truth-conditional and non-truth-conditional meaning.

Gazdar On this approach, pragmatics would deal with a range of disparate phenomena, including a Gricean conversational inference, b the inferential recognition of illocutionary-force, and c the conventional meanings of illocutionary-force indicators and other non-truth-conditional expressions such as but, please, unfortunately Recanati From the cognitive point of view, these phenomena have little in common.

Within the cognitive science literature in particular, the semantics-pragmatics distinction is now more generally seen as coextensive with the distinction between decoding and inference or conventional and conversational meaning.

On this approach, all conventional meaning, both truth-conditional and non-truth-conditional, is left to linguistic semantics, and the aim of pragmatic theory is to explain how the gap between sentence meaning and utterance interpretation is inferentially bridged.

A pragmatic theory of this type is developed in D. Sperber and D. Wilson This claim has been challenged, and alternative accounts of metaphor and irony developed, in which no maxim-violation takes place Blakemore , Hugly and Sayward , Sperber and Wilson This raises the question of where the borderline between explicit and implicit communication should be drawn Sperber and Wilson , It has even been argued that many of Grices best-known cases of generalized conversational implicature might be better analyzed as pragmatically determined aspects of what is said Carston , Recanati Grices distinction between saying and implicating crosscuts the semantics-pragmatics distinction as defined above.

For Grice, what is said corresponds to the truthconditional content of an utterance, and what is implicated is everything communicated that is not part of what is said.

Grice saw the truth-conditional content of an utterance as determined partly by the conventional semantic meaning of the sentence uttered, and partly by contextual pragmatic factors governing disambiguation and reference assignment. He saw conventional semantic implicatures as determined by the meaning of discourse connectives such as but, moreover and so, and analyzed them as signaling the performance of higherorder speech acts such as contrasting, adding and explaining Grice An alternative analysis is developed in D.

Blakemore Among nonconventional pragmatic implicatures, the best known are the conversational ones: These are beliefs that have to be attributed to the speaker in order to preserve the assumption that she was obeying the cooperative principle with associated maxims of truthfulness, informativeness, relevance, and clarity , in saying what she said.

In Grices framework, generalized conversational implicatures are normally carried by use of a certain expression, and are easily confused with conventional lexical meaning Grice In Grices view, many earlier philosophical analyses were guilty of such confusion. Grices account of conversational implicatures has been questioned on several grounds:. Within the cognitive science literature, several approaches to pragmatics are currently being pursued.

There are computational attempts to implement the Gricean program via rules for the recognition of coherence relations among discourse segments Asher and Lascarides , Hobbs Relations between the Gricean program and speech-act theory are being reassessed Tsohatzidis The cognitive foundations of pragmatics and the relations of pragmatics to neighboring disciplines are still being explored Sperber and Wilson , Sperber Despite this diversity of approaches, pragmatics now seems to be established as a relatively homogenous domain.

As well as disambiguation and reference fixing, there are pragmatic processes of propositional completion, as in the examples in 1 , and, more controversially, processes of free enrichment, as in 2 : 1 a.

Its too late. Cotton is better. Ive had breakfast. Johns car hit Toms and Tom stopped illegally. Bibliography Asher, N. Lexical Disambiguation in a Discourse Context. Journal of Semantics 12 : Blakemore, D. Semantic Constraints on Relevance.

Oxford: Blackwell, Understanding Utterances. Carston, R. Explicature, Implicature and Truth-Theoretic Semantics. Davis, S. Pragmatics: A Reader. New York: Oxford University Press, Gazdar, G. Pragmatics: Implicature, Presupposition and Logical Form.

New York: Academic Press, Grice, H. Logic and Conversation. If you have purchased a print title that contains an access token, please see the token for information about how to register your code. For questions on access or troubleshooting, please check our FAQs , and if you can''t find the answer there, please contact us. All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a title in Oxford Handbooks Online for personal use for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice.

Oxford Handbooks Online. Publications Pages Publications Pages. Recently viewed 0 Save Search. Introduction: What is Pragmatics? The Oxford Handbook of Pragmatics. To summarize our views, at the ideological level our current policies and practices transform human relations into a marketplace; for others, they foster an alienating individualism and invite an instrumentalist orienta- tion to relationships.

In terms of societal well-being, otherwise solid test- ing practices invite distrust and alienation, create divisive hierarchies of worth, undermine pluralistic values, and erode the capacities for local self- direction.

In the local school setting, teachers find that standards-based accountability means narrowing curriculum and pedagogical practices and a loss in motivation. Students find their self-worth placed in question and little in school that excites their interest.

Parents find their nurturing orientation toward their children replaced by a performance based evalu- ative posture. Although one could argue for adjusting current policies and practices cf.

In this context it is useful to consider innovative initiatives. Although there are many such initiatives extant, we outline here several that are illuminating in their avoidance of hierarchical structures. Each favors pluralism, localism, democratic process, qualitative understand- ing, and processes of improvement over product. Rather than striving for summative statements about existing conditions, they focus on generating more flourishing futures Dinesen, Developed by David Fetterman , Fetterman and Wandersman , and Fetterman and Wandersman , the at- tempt is to shift the site of evaluation from the distant overseer to the lo- cal participants.

And, rather than simply assessing students and teachers, the attempt is to enable the local community to become self-directing, to deliberate on its activities, set goals for itself, and take necessary actions. Empowerment evaluators, in this case, serve as coaches or facilitators, helping local communities to build ongoing practices of self-evaluation.

The various groups engaged in implementation also establish yardsticks by which they can evaluate their progress.

Over time educational communities are enabled to chart their future, evaluate their progress, and alter plans and programs on a continuing basis. This is not to say that outside testing procedures are precluded. Rather, standardized tests can provide information helpful in judging local progress. Rather than dictating policy, test scores become adjuncts to local school development. In brief, dialogic evaluation practices tend to emphasize egalitarian dialogue, equality and justice, multicultural intelligences, dialogic learn- ing, and qualitative analysis as opposed to quantification—all with an eye to broad scale social transformation.

Dialogic evalu- ation practices have been explored more visibly in the European context than the American. For example, the English National Board for Nursing, Midwifery and Health Visiting emphasizes the use of context-based dia- logue, centering on competence in practice, along with portfolios that can be used to reflect, envision, and plan. Relevant work in the European Union has stressed the need for training practitioners in the use of dia- logic evaluation.

However, the rele- vance to the educational sphere is clearly apparent. Thus, dialogues that center on prob- lems—for example, the poor performance of students, teachers, or school systems—solidify the reality of the problems.

And when fortified, this re- ality will lead to mutual blame, alienation, distrust, disrespect, lowered motivation, and more. Narratives of positive performance are shared and collected, and dialogue then turns to the common values represented in these narratives. Reflection on these values then moves to the means of building futures in which these values would be most fully instantiated. What concrete steps would be useful and promising?

Groups are then established to monitor progress toward the shared goals. Appreciative practices attempt to bring all stakeholders together in future building. In the educational sphere, this might involve the student, his or her teachers, parents, and possibly others. Learning and knowledge are not so much understood as inside the head of the learner as embodied in the relational actions and prac- tices taking place in the learning environment. These four explorations into alternative ways of thinking about and practicing evaluation are salutary, but at the same time, are only exempla- ry of a movement of a far greater scope.

One might contrast, for example, the stringent and high stakes practices of testing in Japan and Korea with the low levels of stan- dardized testing in Finland. By the same token, one may ask about the ways in which these differing practices function in society. Interestingly, while the strong testing approaches taken in Japan and Korea are asso- ciated with high rates of adolescent suicide along with laws to prevent excessive study , Finnish minimalism is coterminal with what is regarded to be the most effective educational system in the world.

Further explo- ration of such differences would be useful in expanding deliberation on alternatives to present practices. Yet, as we proposed at the outset of our initial paper, technology-based shifts in global conditions appear to militate against current testing prac- tices in the United States. The attempt to impose a single set of standards on an enormously varied domain of practices fails to recognize the rapidly shifting and endlessly complex landscape of educational desiderata.

What is needed in the way of education—the knowledge and the skills required for productive and meaningful participation—is ever changing. To lock in a highly circumscribed set of ideals and to shape the entire educational system by these specifications is to reduce the potential for productive participation in the future.

Further, these same technologies of commu- nication also foster multiple affinity groups, enabling them to generate rationales, agendas, and plans of action. In effect, there is an expansion in the array of voices that demand to be heard, voices that are set against oth- erwise totalizing agendas.

In our view, the way must be prepared for more democratic, inclusive, and dialogic contributions to the ways in which lo- cal systems of education function. Let us briefly summarize what we see as the major outcomes of our delib- erations. Assessment should in no way drive these efforts, but should serve ancillary or supportive functions. In what follows, we first attend to what we believe assessment should not be and then shift the focus to what, for us, assessment should become.

To be clear, we are not arguing against active and continuing delibera- tions on the performance adequacy of students, teachers, administrators, or school systems in general.

Such reflections can make vital contributions to educational success in rapidly changing and highly differentiated world conditions. Assessment instruments or tests can contribute to such delib- erations in significant ways. What could this mean for the future of testing and measurement instru- ments more generally? In our view the above recommendations would not mean a diminishment, but rather, an enrichment and expansion of such services.

Whether and how local school systems or dis- tricts employ test scores in their deliberations should be locally determined. For example, depending on locale, schools might wish to have tests that would enable them to benchmark students in terms of computer literacy, career fluency, civic and political participation, bilingual capacity, dialogic, skills, environmental knowledge, musi- cal aptitude, physical competence, health, and so on.

For example, schools might vary- ingly wish to benchmark themselves in terms of parental participa- tion, excellence as a learning community, internal collaboration, civic contribution, relationships with business and government, and the like.

In conclusion, if we take into account the increasing development of communication technologies and the resulting shifts in demands and op- portunities, it is imperative to explore new ways of practicing evaluation.

Along with Nussbaum , we argue here for assessment in the service of creating capabilities as opposed to judging them. Ramachaudran Ed. New York: Academic Press.

Bellah, R. Habits of the heart: Individuals and commitment in American life. Berkeley: University of CA Press. Center for Education Policy. Coghlan, A. An overview of appreciative inquiry in evaluation. New Directions for Evaluation, Winter. Cousins, J. Framing participatory evaluation. Whitmore Ed. Hoboken: Jossey Bass. Dahler-Larsen, P. The evaluation society. Derrida, J. Of grammatology. Dinesen, M. Systemic appreciative evaluation: Developing quality instead of just measuring it.

AI Practitioner, 11, 49— Inheritance and an economy of difference: The importance of supplementary education. Lin, E. Varenne Eds. Epistemology and measurement: Paradigms and practices I: A critical perspective on the sciences of measurement. The aim and structure of physical theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Originally published in Fetterman, D. Foundations of empowerment evaluation.

Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Fetterman, D. Empowerment evaluation, principles in practice. New York: Guilford. Empowerment evaluation, yesterday, today, and tomorrow. American Journal of Evaluation, 28, — Fishman, S. Unplayed tapes: A personal history of teacher research. New York: Teachers College Press. Fleck, L. Genesis and development of scientific fact. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Originally published in Foucault, M. Translate PDF. A Summary of Pragmatics in Linguistics Linguistics as the scientific study of language consists of several branches.

These include phonetics, phonology, syntax, semantics and pragmatics. While semantics studies the meaning conveyed by words, pragmatics studies the meaning as conveyed by the speaker and interpreted by the listener. This so-called speaker's meaning has become the subject of many theories in pragmatics, namely speech act theory, Grice's maxims and Penelope's Politeness principle. The first theory which attempted to explain speaker's meaning is the so-called speech act theory by Austin and Searle.

The basic definition of a speech act is the action we can do with language. The different actions we do by language have been classified into taxonomies, namely assertives, directives, commisssive, expressives and declaratives. These speech acts can be analysed by three levels locutionary, perlocutionary and illocutionary. The locutionary aspect refers to the syntactic and semantic structure of an utterance.

The perlocutionary aspect is the real intended meaning.



0コメント

  • 1000 / 1000